“On Why the Evidence does not Licence Fine-Tuning Arguments”
A Contribution to a Book Symposium on John Leslie’s Modern Cosmology and Philosophy
Canadian Philosophical Association and Canadian Society of Christian Philosophers
Laval University, 26 May 2001
 
WILLIAM L. VANDERBURGH
Wichita State University

 

It can’t be doubted: we live in a universe in which life is possible. What is in some doubt is just what to make of this fact. My view of the matter is that very little can be made of this fact, given the present state of cosmological knowledge. My comments today will bear on the issue of whether or not there are fundamental cosmological parameters that are “fine-tuned” for life; where we shall take “fine-tuning” to mean simply that the parameters could have been different, and if they had been ever so slightly different the universe would not have been hospitable to life.
 

Cosmologists generally take it that there is strong evidence for fine-tuning. Some philosophers have tried to make Design Arguments from this evidence for fine-tuning to the existence of a creative entity such as God; more specifically, some have tried to argue that either fine-tuning implies a Designer, or it implies the existence of multiple worlds. In the latter case we explain the seeming specialness of fine-tuning by appeal to the Anthropic Principle. I’m not go to weigh in on this debate at all. I happen to agree with Hume that Design arguments are fundamentally flawed, but my point today is elsewhere. What I want to do is to show that certain fundamental assumptions in modern cosmology are very much less well established than is commonly taken to be the case. In particular I will argue for two points. First, that in fact we have no evidence that General Relativity (GR) applies to the universe as a whole, and second, that it might be impossible to obtain any evidence that would make us confident in the applicability of GR or any other theory of gravitation to the cosmos as a whole.
 

GR is of course Einstein’s relativistic theory of space, time and gravitation. In its gravitational aspect GR is a fundamental ingredient in almost every idea in cosmology, from the origin, expansion and age of the universe, to large scale structure, to galactic evolution and stellar fusion; in other words, cosmology is shot through with GR. If I’m right that the evidential warrant for GR in most of these contexts is actually not very strong, and is perhaps not improvable, a great many of the “facts” of cosmology are consequently quite a bit less well established than is commonly taken to be the case. The corollary of this that is of interest here is that much of the supposed evidence for fine-tuning will turn out to be not very strong. If this is so, we should put aside attempts even to say that the universe appears to be fine-tuned, let alone attempts to make inferences from the supposed fine-tuning to some philosophical conclusion about God or multiple worlds.
 

Now, my argument is just concerning GR, so only those fine-tuning arguments that involve GR are directly cast into doubt by the reasoning I will present. There might be other cases of fine-tuning (say, regarding the ratio of the nuclear forces) that do not rely on GR, and upon which one could more reliably construct Design or other types of arguments. I will leave these cases aside, except to say two things. First, note that if most of cosmology—that is, the very large proportion of it that relies on GR—is of too low epistemic standing to license philosophical arguments, whatever is left over will probably not be enough to mount a convincing argument about Design or multiple worlds. It seems to me we would need pervasive evidence of fine-tuning to even get off the ground, and the remainders of fine-tuning left over after my argument are probably insufficient for this purpose. Second, the reasons for doubting the epistemic standing of GR as applied to the cosmos also raise possible doubts about the other theories upon which the remainder fine-tuning evidence relies.
 

My own interests in modern cosmology have to do with evidence and methodology. I think that cosmological theorizing and especially the creative ways in which cosmologists bring evidence to bear on their theories, is of immense philosophical interest—in particular as an example of empirical reasoning under extremely evidence-poor and otherwise epistemically difficult conditions. Even though my view is that this difficult epistemic position means that the evidence for cosmological theories is really not very strong (compared, say, to our evidence about celestial mechanics, or terrestrial geology), I still agree with cosmologists who are eager to insist that modern cosmology is a science. It is just that it seems inevitable that our evidence for cosmological theories will never be epistemically comparable to, say, our theories of biological evolution. This is something that should inspire in us an appropriate caution when we are tempted to draw philosophical conclusions from the current state of cosmology.
 

With these preliminaries out of the way, let me turn now to the argument itself. What got me thinking along these lines were some papers by G.F.R. Ellis, including one anthologized by Leslie. Let me turn now to discussing Ellis’s position on GR in the context of cosmological spacetime structure. Afterwards I will go on to consider the evidential status of GR in astrophysics and cosmology. Here I’ll be drawing on some of my own work on the dynamical dark matter problem to show that we don’t have good reason to think that GR applies to galaxies or larger dynamical structures, let alone to the universe as a whole.
 

General Relativity predicts and explains, to a very high degree of precision, a wide variety of phenomena. The main phenomena in question are the motions of bodies in the solar system (including Mercury’s excess perihelion precession), the gravitational redshift of light, the Shapiro time delay for signals passing near the Sun, the gravitational bending of light rays by massive bodies, and the formation of black holes. GR has been shown to account for all these phenomena better than every alternative gravitational theory that has yet been constructed (see Will, 1993). GR’s successes are nothing if not impressive, and surely they do confer a great deal of epistemic warrant on the theory. As it turns out, however, all these are tests on stellar system scales, and they are really the only available tests for theories of gravitation. All the epistemic warrant for GR, therefore, concerns its applicability to stellar system scales. I’ll use the phrase “stellar system scales” to refer to systems roughly similar to our solar system in size; I want to include gravitational interactions up to this scale, even though almost all of the tests just mentioned involve interactions at much shorter scales, because GR also successfully accounts for the decay of the orbits of binary pulsars through its prediction of the emission of gravitational radiation.[1]
 

The success of GR with regard to these tests is usually taken to provide warrant for the applicability of GR to larger dynamical systems such as galaxies and clusters of galaxies, and even to the evolution and structure of the universe as a whole. But the applicability of GR at larger scales can be no more than an assumption in the present evidential context. (See Mannheim 1994 and Ellis 1975, 1980, 1985, 1999.) As with Newton’s argument to Universal Gravitation, we perform an inductive generalization upon a set of “locally-derived” pieces of evidence, where this evidence is consistent with itself and ideally involves independent measures of theoretical parameters from several phenomena. Newton’s extension of the principle of mutual gravitation to all bodies is the step of the argument on which the inductive risk is focused (Smith 1999). As we know, Newton’s bet here failed: extending Universal Gravity to all phenomena on the basis of short-scale, weak-field tests, turned out to be incorrect. In the same way, it is evidentially risky to extend GR to all dynamical systems regardless of scale merely on the basis of stellar system or shorter scale tests. This might not be cause for worry except that there is evidence that suggests that GR might in fact be inapplicable at galactic and greater scales—that is, that analogously to the way Newtonian Universal Gravitation is the low-velocity, weak-field limit of GR, GR could be the short-scale limit of some other yet-to-be-discovered relativistic gravitation theory that applies at galactic and greater scales.
 

Let me take the two relevant cases in turn, starting with the evidence for GR’s applicability to the universe as a whole, and then the evidence for GR’s applicability to large scale dynamical systems. Ellis (1985) has argued persuasively that cosmology not only in fact relies on unverified assumptions (for example, the Cosmological Principle and the Copernican Principle, which state respectively that the universe is homogeneous and isotropic, and that we do not occupy a privileged or unusual region of the universe), but that cosmology must necessarily rely on untestable assumptions. Ellis argues, among other things, that the very nature of the project of cosmology is such that we cannot determine by means of any purely observational test what the large scale structure of spacetime is. This in turn means that it is also impossible to test which law of gravitation holds for the universe as a whole: such a law can only be tested provided that we know well the very factors Ellis argues are unavailable to us.
 

The details of Ellis’s argument are beyond the scope of the present discussion. It suffices to note that there are two factors that lead to his result. First, in order to verify any of the main properties of Friedmann-Robertson-Walker (FRW) universes[2], one has to assume some or all of the others (no independent check of each of the properties is possible). Second, alternative non-FRW cosmological models can always be found which would account for the observations just as well as any FRW model does. The clearest case which shows that the characteristics of FRW universes cannot be tested independently is the case of distortion effects. A distortion effect is a change in the appearance of a distant object as compared to what it would look like across a completely flat spacetime, a change induced by the passage of the light from that object through a region of spacetime which is distorted (that is, not flat). Distortion effects can be induced by gravitational lensing by matter, or the distortion can be caused by large-scale properties of the spacetime itself. In an FRW universe there would be no distortion effects (the global spacetime curvature is zero, and the matter distribution perfectly homogeneous and isotropic). We would therefore need to confirm that there are no distortion effects in order to confirm that our universe is actually FRW. But we cannot check for distortions in the images of distant objects unless we know what shape they have originally, and obviously we do not have this information. We cannot, for example, rule out the possibility that the objects that we call elliptical galaxies are really spherical objects seen through a distorting spacetime. Even if we were to treat every source as a point source, finding a perfectly homogeneous and isotropic distribution of sources across the entire sky would not prove that there is no distortion effect. This evidence would be just as consistent with an actually homogeneous and isotropic source distribution as it would be with any number of inhomogeneous and anisotropic distributions taken together with suitably selected global distortion effects. A homogeneous and isotropic apparent distribution of sources is indeed consistent with the assumption that the universe is FRW—but observing such a distribution obviously does not prove that the assumptions of the model are right.
 

Ellis’s argument casts into doubt Will’s claim (1993, 310-19) that cosmology has been a testing ground for gravitation theory since the 1920s. It is true that various cosmological observations (for example, the Hubble recession and the cosmic microwave background) have been taken as confirming that the universe satisfies the Big Bang model, and therefore the FRW spacetime model (which the Big Bang assumes), and therefore General Relativity (because the FRW model is a solution to the GR field equations). But if Ellis’s arguments are correct, this supposed confirmation is illusory or extremely weak, amounting to no more than showing that GR is consistent with the available cosmological observations relative to some intuitively plausible but rather strong and evidentially unsupported assumptions. Relative to different (and equally unsupported) assumptions, the cosmological evidence is equally consistent with universe models very different from the FRW model (for example, ones that are not isotropic or have regions of intrinsic spacetime curvature). If we had some way of confirming one set of assumptions over the others, we could perhaps make some progress toward deciding what the true large scale structure of the universe is, and this would allow us to confirm a theory of gravitation at cosmic scales. But if, as Ellis argues, there is no way to determine empirically whether or not the universe is in fact homogeneous and isotropic, it is necessarily the case that there is no way to determine with confidence which spacetime model fits the universe best.
 

With the argument for cosmological scales behind us, let me now turn to the issue of the evidential basis for applying GR to the scales of galaxies and clusters. The fact that GR is not tested at scales larger than a stellar system can be demonstrated by considering the evidence that is taken to support GR, which I mentioned earlier. What these tests have in common is that they involve interactions taking place over relatively short scales, at most about the size of a stellar system. These successful tests of General Relativity at short scales are certainly consistent with GR being the correct gravitational theory at very large distances, but they do not give us direct evidence that this is indeed the case—the evidence is also consistent with a very different gravitational action at large scales. Newton’s argument to “Universal” Gravitation did not establish empirically that other stars gravitate but rather used the available evidence of gravitation among nearby bodies plus some principles of theory choice (Newton’s Rules of Reasoning) as the foundation for making an inductive extension of the local law to all bodies. In the same way, the hypothesis that GR applies at large scales is not supported empirically by direct evidence.
 

In fact, one can construct an argument to suggest that the dynamical evidence from galaxies and clusters contradicts the hypothesis that GR holds at those scales. I am referring here to the evidence of the dynamical dark matter problem, which has to do with the fact that measurements of the masses of astrophysical systems such as galaxies and clusters of galaxies taken from their motions are up to two orders of magnitude greater than the mass estimates taken from the matter visible in these systems. This discrepancy can be resolved in one of two ways. Either we can trust the gravitational law through which the masses are measured dynamically and postulate the existence of up to 100 times more matter than is visible in these systems (this matter is called “dark” because we cannot detect any electromagnetic radiation from it); or we can trust the visible mass estimates and revise the gravitational law at these scales so as to be able to recover the motions without needing to introduce unseen matter. (Note that I am not here talking about the cosmological dark matter problem, which is another kettle of fish altogether.)
 

The argument to suggest that no gravitational theory can be tested at galactic and greater scales is based on what I call “the dark matter double bind”, which goes as follows. Note that in order to test a gravitational theory, one must show (minimally) that it correctly predicts the motions of a system of bodies, given some initial configuration of that system. To specify the initial configuration, one must specify the distribution of bodies as well as their masses and velocities. Thus in order to test GR using the motions of a given spiral galaxy, say, one needs to know in advance what the mass distribution is. But the very existence of the dynamical dark matter problem calls into doubt the assumption that the visible matter is all the matter that exists in galaxies. In fact, we have no warranted idea about what the matter distribution might be. Conversely, if we had reason to think that some particular dynamical law was true of the galaxy, we could use this dynamical law in concert with observations of the motions of visible matter to reliably infer the overall mass distribution. But, as I have suggested above, we have no evidence to confirm that GR (or any other law) applies to galaxies. Thus, we cannot obtain a dynamical test of a gravitational theory at galactic and greater scales unless we assume the matter distribution in advance, and we cannot empirically determine the matter distribution unless we first know which dynamical law applies. That’s the dark matter double bind.
 

There might be ways around this conclusion in the future. For example, we might learn to be able to “see” dark matter, in which case we could then use the overall distribution of dark and visible matter together with the motions in a galaxy to determine which gravitational law governs that system. But in the present evidential context the existence of the dynamical dark matter discrepancy for astrophysical systems prevents us from being able to test GR (or any gravitational theory) at scales greater than those of a stellar system. As I have suggested, since GR is assumed in almost every part of modern cosmology, the unavailability of tests of GR means that most cosmological theories must in fact be only weakly warranted in the present evidential context. This, I claim, means that whatever evidence we currently have for fine-tuning is too insecure to license any inferences, whether about a Designer or the existence of multiple worlds, from that supposed fine-tuning.
 

 

Refenences

 

Ellis, G.F.R. (1999). “The Different Nature of Cosmology,” Astronomy and Geophysics, August 1999, 4.20-4.23.

 

Ellis, G.F.R. (1985). “Observational Cosmology After Kristian and Sachs,” in Stoeger (1985), 475-86.

 

Ellis, G.F.R. (1980). “Limits to Verification in Cosmology,” Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 336, 130-60.

 

Ellis, G.F.R. (1975). “Cosmology and Verifiability,” Quarterly Journal of the Royal Astronomical Society, 16, 245-64.

 

Leslie, John. (ed.) (1998). Modern Cosmology and Philosophy. Second, enlarged edition of Physical Cosmology and Philosophy (1990). Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.

 

Mannheim, Philip D. (1994). “Open Questions in Classical Gravity,” Foundations of Physics, 24.4, 487-511.

 

Smith, George. (1999a). “From the Phenomenon of the Ellipse to an Inverse-Square Force: Why Not?” Philosophy Department Colloquium, University of Western Ontario, 24 September 1999.

 

Vanderburgh, William L. (2001). Dark Matters in Contemporary Astrophysics: A Case Study in Theory Choice and Evidential Reasoning. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Western Ontario.

 

Will, Clifford M. (1993). Theory and Experiment in Gravitation Physics. Revised edition (first edition 1981). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.



[1] The gravitational lensing of the light of background objects by foreground galaxies is a special case I can discuss in the question period if anyone is interested. (See: Vanderburgh 2001.)
[2] An FRW universe is a solution to the Einstein field equations for the whole universe, one that assumes a zero intrinsic curvature and a perfectly homogeneous and isotropic matter distribution. Among the interdependent properties of FRW universes identified by Ellis and homogeneity, isotropy, distortion effects and global curvature.